Aristotelian Virtue Ethics
Aristotelian Virtue Ethics: Key Concepts
- Eudaimonia: Derived from Greek meaning ‘flourishing’, Aristotle used this term to refer to ultimate human goal or the ‘highest good’. It is often translated as ‘happiness’ in a broad sense.
- Virtue (Arete): The character traits that enable us to function well as humans and thus achieve eudaimonia. Virtues are habits of behaviour that are developed through practice.
- Doctrine of the Mean: Aristotle’s approach to finding the balance between extremes in order to determine virtuous behaviour. Every virtue is a mean between two vices, one of excess and one of deficiency.
- Phronesis (Practical Wisdom): The intellectual virtue needed to discern how best to act virtuously.
Understanding Aristotelian Virtue Ethics
- Virtue Ethics places focus on the character of the moral agent rather than the act itself (deontology) or the consequences of the act (consequentialism).
- Virtue ethics is agent-centred rather than action-centred. The ethical life is more about the person and their character than the actions they perform.
- Aristotle proposed that human beings have a purpose (telos) which is to achieve eudaimonia.
- Virtues are cultivated through habituation. In other words, by repeatedly performing virtuous actions, we become virtuous.
Criticisms of Aristotelian Virtue Ethics
- One key criticism is that Virtue Ethics is too vague and does not provide clear guidance on what actions should be taken in moral dilemmas.
- There are also issues relating to cultural relativism, as what is seen as a virtue in one culture might not be seen as such in another.
- Some might argue that the idea of a fixed human nature or telos is outdated and does not align with modern understandings of psychology and sociology.
Responses to the Criticisms
- In response to the criticism of vagueness, virtue ethicists argue that ethics requires a nuanced approach that takes into account the specific contexts and characters involved rather than prescribing a ‘one-size-fits-all’ rule.
- To the critique of cultural relativism, virtue ethicists may respond that while specific virtues might vary, the underlying values, such as respect, courage or kindness, can be universally applicable.
- As for the criticism of a fixed human nature, virtue ethicists might argue that while the specifics of human nature may evolve, the basic capacity for rationality and social interaction remains a cornerstone of humanity, which their theory accounts for.